Suppose $n$ houses are to be assigned to $n$ people. Each person ranks the houses in the order of preference, with no ties. After the assignment is made, it is observed that every other assignment would assign to at least one person a less preferred house. Prove that there is at least one person who received the house he/she preferred most under this assignment.
Problem
Source: Turkey TST 1998 Problem 4
Tags: combinatorics proposed, combinatorics
25.12.2011 14:53
Let enumerate the people $1,2,\cdots,n $. Let denote the house which is assigned to the man numbered $n$ as $n$. In this way $n$-th house is assigned to $n$-th man. List of preferencies of $i$-th man can be represent by a permutation $\sigma_{i}$. Now, in oreder to prove the assertion, let assume on the contrary that $\sigma_i(1) \neq i,\, i=1,2,\cdots,n$. The idea is to construct a permutation $\sigma$ (not equal to id) for which $\sigma(i) = i $ or $\sigma(i) = \sigma_i(1)$. If such a permutation exists then it will be a contradiction with the problem clause. Let $a_1 = 1, \, b_1 = \sigma_1(1);\, a_{i+1} = b_i,\, b_{i+1} = \sigma_{a_{i+1}}(1)$. Note that $b_i \neq a_i$. In this way there will be a moment when for the first time $b_k = b_s,\, s < k$. Then we define the permutation $\sigma$ as follows: If $ i=a_j $ for some $ j=s+1,s+2,\cdots, k $ then $\sigma(i) = b_j $ else $\sigma(i) = i$.
05.01.2018 04:47
More dirty-hands type of approach: Denote the house assigned to $i^{th}$ person as $a_i$. Start with an arbitrary person $i_1$, who did not receive his top choice. Suppose that, his top choice is $a_{i_2}$ (namely, with person $i_2$). Switching these two houses makes the first person better off, hence, in $i_2$'s list, $a_{i_2}>a_{i_1}$, otherwise would contradict with the preamble. In particular, $i_2$'s top choice is not $a_{i_1}$. Now, if $i_2$ has his top house, we are done. Otherwise, suppose, $a_{i_3}$ is his top choice. We make the following observations: Claim: $i_3$'s top choice is neither $a_{i_1}$, nor $a_{i_2}$. Proof:Clearly, it is not $a_{i_2}$, since, swapping $a_{i_2}$ and $a_{i_3}$ makes $i_2$ better off, it must make $i_3$ worse, hence, in $i_3$'s list, $a_{i_3}>a_{i_2}$. To see why it cannot be $a_{i_1}$ either, notice that had it been, then, the following assignment, $$ (i_1 \mapsto a_{i_2}, i_2 \mapsto a_{i_3}, i_3 \mapsto a_{i_1}), $$gives us everyone's top choice, a contradiction. Hence, $i_3$'s top choice is some other $i_4$. Claim: $i_4$'s top choice is neither $a_{i_1}$, nor $a_{i_2}$ or $a_{i_3}$. Proof: This is a mere repetition of the previous argument. For the sake of completeness, it is included. First, it cannot be $i_3$ (follows from swapping $i_3$ and $i_4$). Had it been $i_2$, then, $$ (i_2\mapsto a_{i_3},i_3 \mapsto a_{i_4},i_4 \mapsto a_{i_2}), $$would assign at least three people to their top choices, a contradiction. Finally, to see why it cannot be $a_{i_1}$, notice that, this time, we need, $$ (i_1\mapsto a_{i_2},i_2\mapsto a_{i_3},i_3\mapsto a_{i_4},i_4\mapsto a_{i_1}), $$again, contradicts with the statement. Hence, continuing in this manner, at each step, $i_k$'s top choice is none of $a_{i_j},j=1,2,\dots,k-1$. Hence, we must stop at somewhere, $i_n$, and for this person, his top choice is none of $a_{i_1},a_{i_2},\dots,a_{i_{n-1}}$, thus, he must be assigned to his top choice.